ashhughes

A Collection of Essays

Nietzsche and the Enlightenment

with 2 comments

A response to Nietzsche’s ‘On Truth and Lies in a Nonmoral Sense’

The philosophy of Friedrich Nietzsche is often rightly considered a break with the Enlightenment. However, a close reading of his 1873 essay ‘On Truth and Lies in a Nonmoral Sense’ reveals that it very much is a work of the Enlightenment, in that it deals with some of its claims and key concerns. Herein, we can discover thoughts on human nature, society, morality, rational man and truth. But do we need to understand Nietzsche himself to understand the ideas in his writing? The substance of the essay in question suggests Nietzsche might be unsympathetic to our claims of understanding. Indeed, were such a thing as understanding possible, in the case of Friedrich Nietzsche, it might yet still remain impossible.

Two popular interpretations of Nietzsche have been; first, that he was a sort of proto-Nazi, an idea which has since been discredited as stemming from deliberate misinterpretation and integration of his work into Nazi philosophy; and second, that his writings were contradictory and inconsistent, which has in part been blamed by scholars on Nietzsche’s sister, who herself edited and published some of his work posthumously. Nietzsche perhaps would not have been concerned with inconsistency or contradiction. His writings are very different in style to the orderly presentation of Descartes’ ‘Discourse on the Method’ or Kant’s ‘Idea for a Universal History’, and yet, especially in the case of this essay in question, they remain  powerful, lucid and rich.

Nietzsche is well known for the proclamation ‘God is Dead’. The controversial phrasing means this expression is not surprisingly often misunderstood, but for Nietzsche it means that the idea, the belief, the possibility, the illusion and the need for god is dead. Heidegger understood this as the death of metaphysics, although Nietzsche himself saw the metaphysical need as an offshoot of religion, rather than a precursor to religion. But if there is no god, then the foundation of morality and truth is removed, and anything might be possible. Nietzsche realized that the consequences of this could be terrible.

Dorinda Outram describes a common interpretation of the Enlightenment as

a desire for human affairs to be guided by rationality rather than by faith, superstition, or revelation; a belief in the power of human reason to change society and liberate the individual from the restraints of custom or arbitrary authority; all backed up by a world view increasingly validated by science rather than by religion or tradition.[1]

Against this reading, it is relatively unproblematic to present Nietzsche as a break with the Enlightenment project. Indeed, Nietzsche is often placed by scholars as a descendant of the German Romantic movement. This movement was in part a reaction to the ideal of rationalism as presented by the Enlightenment. He was influenced by or admired men such as Schopenhauer, Stendhal, Dostoyevsky, Voltaire, Wagner, among many others, although many would eventually fall out of his favour. As an anti-Enlightenment thinker, Nietzsche seriously questioned the idea of progress, and of the perfectibility of man or society.

While some writers such as Hobbes and Rousseau have rather distinct views of human nature when it is not constrained by society, Nietzsche, in this piece, has little interest in portraying human nature as either fundamentally good or bad. Human nature is what it is. What others with a pessimistic view of human nature might call bad, would perhaps be of little concern to Nietzsche. Indeed, it is precisely the capacity and desire for deception in man which shields him from the true nature of his existence,

And woe to that fatal curiosity which might one day have the power to peer out and down through a crack in the chamber of consciousness and then suspect that man is sustained in the indifference of his ignorance by that which is pitiless, greedy, insatiable, and murderous.[2]

While Nietzsche may have been angered by some of the ‘life-denying’ aspects of Christian morality, there is a sense that despite this general ‘self-deception’ toward human nature, he might have tentatively approved, if not with the means then at least with the end. According to Graeme Garrard, Nietzsche “thought that Voltaire had correctly realized that man is a ‘beast of prey’ and that civilization is a ‘tremendous triumph’ over his bestial nature.”[3]

One cannot help but get the impression from Nietzsche that he felt society to be limiting both to species and individual. In Nietzsche’s view of society, where ‘truth’ and morality are derived from using the established conventions, there arises a contradiction or tension between the unrestricted inquiry encouraged by the Enlightenment and the stability of the society. This can be linked to Nietzsche’s concept of herd morality, where truth means using the accepted designations for things, and the resisting of both lies and truths which could prove harmful. Unrestricted inquiry could challenge the accepted metaphors. But Nietzsche, as evidenced by his essay, does not hesitate to question the accepted metaphors and concepts.

For Nietzsche, it remains that man chooses for himself these limitations to form a society

From boredom and necessity, man wishes to exist socially and with the herd; therefore, he needs to make peace and strives accordingly to banish from his world at least the most flagrant bellum omnium contra omnes – war of all against all.[4]

The use of the phrase ‘war of all against all’ demonstrates an intellectual link with Hobbes,[5] and is at odds with Rousseau’s conception of man in the ‘state of nature’. For Nietzsche, society is at least a ‘cease-fire’ if not a peace treaty, and also a first step in the origin of the puzzling human drive for ‘truth’.[6]

While society here may be considered a choice, humans are almost always born into society, the only choice being perhaps the unlikely decision to leave it. The consensus of society may equally be one of superstition, rather than that of reasoned explanation. According to Garrard, “Nietzsche enthusiastically commends the Enlightenment for its attacks on Christianity and its elitist disdain for la canaille, as Voltaire sometimes contemptuously referred to the masses.”[7]

But this disdain for the unenlightened mass, the mass which may not make as full a use of the faculty of reason, or adequate use of rationalism and skepticism, which may favour traditions and religion over science and critical enquiry; this disdain suggests that a rational education is a prerequisite for human value, for that is what the class whom Voltaire criticized lacked. Despite the heralding of universal and inalienable rights in the political movements which embraced the Enlightenment, it yet remained that the worthy person was the educated person.

In ‘On Truth and Lies in a Nonmoral Sense’, Nietzsche unravels the web of pretensions which comprise the human intellect. The first pretension is the invention of ‘knowing’, the supposed ability to grasp ‘truth’. ‘Knowing’ is the source of pride which validates for man the value of his existence. Intertwined with this pride is deception, which the individual uses several forms of in maintaining himself against others, and which his nature leads him to use against himself.

In relation to the title of this essay, Nietzsche distinguishes lies from truth as a misuse of the fixed conventions of language. Lies or deception are not hated in themselves, but their harmful consequences are. Nietzsche considers any pretension to the possession of pure truth to be the result of forgetfulness; thus any moral obligation toward truth and away from lies is in the service of minimizing harm, and is a social obligation not stemming from any truth in itself.

“So far we have heard only of the duty which society imposes in order to exist: to be truthful means to employ the usual metaphors.”[8] That is, to lie with the herd. The morality of truth is derived from the social obligation to comply with the fixed conventions and metaphors.

For Nietzsche, language demonstrates not only the subjective nature of perception (and thus the myth of objectivity) but also the human disregard for pure truth .

The formation of language is the result of metaphors built upon metaphors into the creation of concepts, which themselves have no direct relationship with the original unique experience, or the thing in itself. This concern partially echoes Descartes geometric argument involving a triangle; we know of a perfect triangle but have “no reason to be assured that there was any such triangle in existence”.[9]

The philosophical claim to truth is parallel to the claim of science to see material reality objectively. Both are impossible as they involve the subject. Logic, reason, time, space and numbers are all constructs, those means by which we attempt to ‘know’ are also the barriers to truth, dividing us from the ‘thing in itself’.

Towards the end of the essay, Nietzsche makes a distinction between intuitive and rational man. What they have in common is that the “drive toward the formation of metaphors is the fundamental human drive”[10]; but this drive is by its nature a creative drive. They are both creative in the sense above, yet have different aims. The creativity of rational man is used in concepts which can be used to guard against the uncertainties of life, whereas intuitive man regards life as something good in itself and uses his creativity to celebrate life. For Nietzsche this is a deception of a different nature, but one he seems more sympathetic towards.

The final paragraph of the essay is used to mock rational man. His ability to learn from and master circumstances which bring misfortune and thus not be perturbed by it, results in his deception being executed precisely when misfortune arises. The rational man who understands weather and can make the causal link between thunderous dark clouds overhead and imminent soaking rain, instead of using this knowledge to protect himself from the elements, must otherwise maintain his dignity and composure, to surrender to the elements he understands precisely because he understands them, rather than to flee from beneath them.

Nietzsche’s ‘On Truth and Lies in a Nonmoral Sense’ constitutes an attack on the very foundation of the Enlightenment project; an undermining of the idea that man can objectively harness this faculty called reason and apply it to the world, in a sense, knowing and wielding truth. But with truth thus undermined, without subsequent destruction of the belief in reason and truth, we are left with a feeling of teetering and sinking, perhaps even of imminent collapse. Nietzsche has torn back the veil of concepts and shown us metaphors, the shedding of a façade revealing a rotting frame, safe perhaps only while all agree that it is so.

 

Bibliography

Descartes, Rene, ‘Discourse on the Method’, in David Weisman (ed.), Discourse on the Method and Meditations on First Philosophy, New Haven, Yale University Press, 1996, pp. 3-26.

Garrard, Graeme, ‘Nietzsche For and Against the Enlightenment’, The Review of Politics, Fall 2008; 70, 4;  pp. 595-608.

Hobbes, Thomas, Leviathan, Harmondsworth, Penguin, 1985.

Nietzsche, Friedrich, ‘On Truth and Lies in a Nonmoral Sense’, in Keith Ansell Pearson and Duncan Large (eds.), The Nietzsche reader, Oxford, Blackwell, 2006, pp. 114-23.

Outram, Dorinda, ‘What is Enlightenment?’, in The Enlightenment, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1995, pp. 1-13.


[1] Dorinda Outram, ‘What is Enlightenment?’, in The Enlightenment, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1995, p. 3.

[2] Friedrich Nietzsche, ‘On Truth and Lies in a Nonmoral Sense’, in Keith Ansell Pearson and Duncan Large (eds.), The Nietzsche reader, Oxford, Blackwell, 2006, p. 117.

[3] Graeme Garrard, ‘Nietzsche For and Against the Enlightenment’, The Review of Politics, Fall 2008; 70, 4;  p. 607.

[4] Nietzsche, p. 115.

[5] Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan, Harmondsworth, Penguin, 1985, p. 185. “They are in that condition which is called Warre; and such a warre, as is of every man, against every man”.

[6] Nietzsche, p. 115.

[7] Garrard, pp. 599-600.

[8] Nietzsche, p. 117.

[9] Rene Descartes, ‘Discourse on the Method’, in David Weisman (ed.), Discourse on the Method and Meditations on First Philosophy, New Haven, Yale University Press, 1996, p. 25.

[10] Nietzsche, p. 121.

Written by ashhughes

April 2, 2012 at 10:00 am

2 Responses

Subscribe to comments with RSS.

  1. Nice job on your citations… Good piece!

    flujan

    April 2, 2012 at 1:54 pm

  2. […] Nietzsche and the Enlightenment (ashhughes.wordpress.com) […]


Leave a comment